CHAPTER 1
1.0 Introduction
The aim of this chapter will include; an attempt to establish the
nature of the controversy between direct and indirect realism right from
the period of John Locke who had established the foundations for the
debate. The rationalists had come to lay a foundation of our knowledge
on supposedly certain and indubitable foundations in reasoning, Locke
too, in his empiricism began to occupy a position referred to as
‘indirect realism’ due to his argument that objects of experience cannot
be directly perceived. But before then, an attempt shall be made to
account for the nature of the argument of the realists as against the
position of the anti-realists’ divide in epistemology. Going back to the
period of the British empiricists with our main point of focus on
Locke, and Berkeley. Having mentioned earlier that there is a divide
between direct and indirect realists, the difference boiling largely out
of how one perceives what one perceives, it will be considerate to
account therefore for the nature of the debate between the both of them
and the attempts of the direct realists to escape the two arguments
(arguments from illusion and hallucination) rendered against it by the
indirect realists.
1.1 Contemporary Realist Arguments
The problem of perception is one that has been in the mind of several
philosophies ever since the period before Socrates, where we see
philosophers like Democritus and Leucippus who claimed that physical
objects are really composed of tiny indivisible particles referred to as
atoms[1].
The problem which is popularly referred to as ‘the problem of
perception’ has been given a new formulation. Epistemologists concerned
with the problem of perception seek to enquire how we come to perceive
the contents of the external world. Before going any further, I shall
try to define what perception itself entails.
Perception is the process by which we, through any of our five
senses- eyes, ears, tongue, nose and skin, gain knowledge of the
external world[2].
It is due to this kind of definition that one is bound to think that it
is something pertaining to empiricism alone. It is indeed a valid
assertion, since it seems to lay emphasis upon the senses and the kind
of connection they have with the world in the bid to acquire knowledge.
We should note that in the light of the above definition, there is a
distinction between what exists in the world, and what we perceive as
existing. According to this conception, there are several theories.
These theories of perception try to answer the question of what and how
we can know through sense experience and they include: realism and
anti-realism.
1.2 Realism vs. Anti-Realism
The argument of the realists is entailed in their conception that
objects of the world exist independent of the mind. For the realists,
every physical thing we perceive would exist even if we were not around
to perceive them, it could therefore be said that for the realists,
perception is mind-independent. That is there does not have to be a mind
before the existence of a physical object could be ascertained. This
implies that the relation between perceiver and the perceived is not of a
dependent form. For the anti-realists however, perception is
mind-dependent. This means that everything that exists only exists
because there is a mind perceiving them. It may look like they are
saying that perception is a temporal thing because the implication will
be that what is not being at the moment perceived by some mind cannot be
claimed to exist until otherwise perceived.
We should note that the above outline of the divide between realists
and anti-realists is that of an old tradition as we shall come to see in
the work of John Locke. It is not the case that their doctrines have
changed, but we shall attempt to account for possible modifications in
the various positions. Our next contention thus, shall be to try to
articulate the positions of contemporary realists in the problem of
perception.
As already outlined above, realism is that epistemological position
in the problem of perception that holds that what we perceive in the
external world is independent of our perceptive faculties. For the
realists, perception is mind independent so that the external world is a
permanent fixate that our senses only come to apprehend whenever we
attempt to perceive.[3] Realists claim that physical objects exist as things that are independent of our minds and of our perceptions of them[4]. A realist believes that there is a world (the “material”
world) that exists independently of whether or not any conscious mind
experiences it. A realist believes that if all the minds (mental beings)
stopped existing tomorrow, there would still be a world out there, just
one that no one was conscious of.
An example of a realist is John Locke, whose philosophy of perception
helped define the lines of indirect realism today. Another is David
Hume who is credited with the saying below:
…this very table, which we see white, and which we feel hard, is
believed to exist, independent of our perception, and to be something
external to our minds, which perceives it.[5]
1.3 Direct Vs. Indirect Realism
Our main aim in this section is to discuss contemporary views on
realism, but this will not be possible if the several views are not
themselves divided into two other schools, the direct/naïve realists,
and the indirect/sophisticated realists.
As much as realism is the school that holds that whatever it is we
perceive, its existence is not dependent on the mind, the position of
the direct/naïve realists is that objects of perception are directly
apprehended, that we have a direct access to the physical objects of the
external world. Direct realists claim that we perceive the physical
objects themselves. When we perceive the world, it certainly appears to
us as it is exactly we directly perceive physical objects that exist
independently of our minds. Direct realism claims that the immediate object of
perception is the physical object itself. We don’t perceive it in
virtue of perceiving something else that ‘mediates’ between our minds
and the physical object.[6]
The indirect realists however are also referred to as representative realists[7].
An example of an indirect realist will be John Locke who claims that
what we perceive are not the objects but an idea of the object in the
world and since an idea is not a physical but a mental thing then it
means that what we perceive according to indirect realism is just an
intermediary between object and perceiver. This means that they advocate
for an intermediary between objects of perception and the perceiver.
The contemporary argument of the representative realists is informed
in their critic of the arguments against the direct realists. This is
using the arguments from illusion and the argument from hallucination.
We shall talk better on this later in this chapter. Bertrand Russell is
an example of an indirect realist, another example is G.E Moore.[8]
1.4 The Empiricism of John Locke
With the aim of the continental rationalists being built on the idea
of innate ideas, which says that every mind is born with ideas, for them
whatever it is we claim to know must have been built upon the certain
ideas that was in our minds at birth. This seemed to make sense, since
their aim was (Descartes for example) to establish a certain foundation
from which all knowledge would emerge, and they thought that the mind
would be that certain foundation in contrast to experience, thus the
doctrine of innatism.[9]
So, in being an empiricist, the aim of John Locke was to unsettle the
previous philosophy before him, rationalism and their doctrine of
innatism, Descartes wanted to provide a solid, indubitable foundation
for knowledge, however Locke viewed rationalism as resting upon
unquestioned assumptions, like the assumption that the mind is born with
ideas at birth, and the further assumption that clarity of concepts can
give accurate knowledge of reality.[10]
It seemed to him, like he’d successfully showed the inadequacy of
the rationalist foundations, so Locke proceeded to assert that the mind
was born at birth blank, empty, this is where his concept of tabula rasa originates.[11]
Unlike the innatists, whatever it is we eventually come to know is not a
function of the mind, but that of experience, from the senses. This
eventually exposed the modest and humble beginnings of Locke’s
epistemology. This is because unlike Descartes who wanted a deductively
certain foundation, Locke agreed that the senses are not certain source
of knowledge (as we shall come to see). This eventually rendered him a
modest empiricist.
Since Locke had asserted that unlike Descartes, the foundation of his
own empiricism is not built on the concept of a blank slate, then it
seemed empirical for him to proceed how it is that our sense from the
outside world help to imprint ideas in the mind.
Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper, void of
all characters, without any ideas: —How comes it to be furnished? Whence
comes it by that vast store which the busy and boundless fancy of man
has painted on it with an almost endless variety? Whence has it all the
materials of reason and knowledge? To this I answer, in one word, from
EXPERIENCE. In that all our knowledge is founded; and from that it
ultimately derives itself.[12]
So, for Locke, experience is the source from which all of our
knowledge arises and not the mind. He described the processes according
to which the sense derived ideas from the external world as the process
of sensation. In sensation the senses gets ideas from the physical
objects out there, and through reflection the mind is able to impose its
characteristic functions of composition and abstraction on the idea
gotten from the external world.
…by reflection then, in the following part of this discourse, I would
be understood to mean, that notice which the mind takes of its own
operations, and the manner of them, by reason whereof there come to be
ideas of these operations in the understanding.[13]
This is the origin of simple and complex ideas in Lockean
epistemology; the eyes for instance perceive a simple object of
sensation like a man and a horse. But the mind, being able to compose
and sometimes abstract the simple ideas gotten from sight is able to
form a further idea of a centaur which although has no existence in
reality. This process of compounding ideas together is referred to as
‘reflection’, the combination of both processes is what gives us the
knowledge that we end up claiming to have, for one without the other is
not sufficient considering that even Locke claimed that in sensation,
the mind is passive, but in reflection, active.
1.4.1 Lockean Indirect Realism
In perceiving the objects of the external world, Locke claims that
what we actually perceive is not the object itself, rather we only
perceive qualities. This will imply that those qualities must in some
way or the other possess a sense of reality, a reality they owe to being
a part of a material object. This may seem like what follows, but in
our distinction between the types of qualities there are, we shall come
to see the idea take some concrete shape. He defines qualities as ‘the
ability of an object to cause ideas in our mind’[14].
This is to take care of the Cartesian question of whether or not the
mind has an accurate representation of the contents of the external
world. It is in his distinction and explanation of the types of
qualities that we have as we shall come to see that the position of
Locke as an indirect realist is explicitly seen.
Since it is the case that we do not always have an accurate
representation of the objects out there, and since Locke had established
that what we perceive are not the objects themselves but only an idea
of them[i],
then it seemed normal for him to posit that in the object themselves
are some qualities, these he called primary and the other are outside of
the object, this he called secondary qualities. Primary qualities are
the qualities that are inherent in the objects of perception, they are
‘primary’ to the objects and once they are abstracted from the object,
then it can never remain the same. They are objective, universal and
include: solidity, extension, figure, mobility, bulk, weight, texture -
“…are utterly inseparable from body…”[15]
The secondary qualities however, are not of the same nature, they do
not reside in the object of perception and are not ‘primary’ to it. They
are only conceived in the minds of the perceiver, they are subjective
and are the representations that the mind perceives in objects. They
include color, taste, smell, sound, [felt] temperature and are caused in
us by primary qualities. They are why we can claim to have perceptual
errors since they are not identical to the object, but are only
comprehended by each perceiver. Unlike the primary qualities therefore,
they are not universal. They are the reasons Locke is considered an
indirect realist today. While the ideas that primary qualities produce
in us resemble those qualities in the objects that caused us to have those ideas, the ideas that secondary qualities produce in us do not resemble those qualities in the objects that caused us to have those ideas.[16]
Whatever realities we may by mistake ascribe to them, colors, smell
sound and taste (secondary qualities) are nothing but qualities produced
in us by the primary or real qualities of objects – sensation, which in
no way resembles the qualities which exists in the object[17]
This explains how it is that there is a distinction between both
primary and secondary qualities as well as the process of perception and
the object of perception. If Locke will go by saying that primary
qualities are the real qualities of objects in being resident in the
object itself, then we perceive much more than these qualities for
existence cannot be denied of the secondary qualities either, this
renders us with evidence for no other conclusion than that since they
differ, they must report separate realities, thus we do not have direct
access to the objects of perception. This is how it is that Locke ends
up being an indirect realist.
The consequence of this is that the world does not appear to us the
way it really is, since secondary qualities are really distinct from the
primary qualities which are seen to be in the object itself, and unlike
the primary qualities, our ideas of secondary qualities do not resemble
the object itself, thus they are only really appearances and are
distinct from the object. The modern version of this notion is entailed
in the indirect realist’s idea of sense data for which Locke is rightly credited for having established foundations for.
1.5 Representationalist Theory of Perception
Having asserted the intricacies of Lockean indirect realism and how
it led us to the conclusion of his being a representationalist in his
claim that , we shall now examine the idea behind the
representationalist theory itself and what it entails in length. The
grounds for the reprsentationalist theory of perception could be found
in the arguments that the indirect realists raised against the direct or
naïve realists. I however shall desist from rendering an explanation to
it in the current section for the next section will be committed to it.
Representationalists say that we perceive ‘indirectly’; what we
perceive ‘directly’ is a ‘representation’, a mental image, that exists
in our minds but which represents the physical object. The physical
object is perceived ‘via’ this representation. The representation is an
‘appearance’; philosophers have called it a ‘sense-datum’.[18]
So for the representationalist, they argue that though we do perceive
the world, there is a difference between how the world looks like, and
how we perceive it. What occurs to our consciousness is different from
what ought to occur for it is a mere representation of reality.
This might sound like a contradiction, but it is the argument of the
indirect realists.
Several philosophers have likened the representationalist distinction
between what exists and what we perceive as being similar to that in
which Aristotle made between appearance (what appears to exist) and
reality (what exists). Since in the representationalist vocabulary, the
physical objects differ from the sense datum, perception is therefore
incomplete until there is sense-datum. We shall attempt outlining some
of the features or characteristics of the sense-datum.
‘Sense data’ was originated by Bertrand Russell, but was first put
into use by G.E Moore, they are seen to be the direct objects of
perception in the indirect realist’s vocabulary. Sense datum is that
which is given directly in perception by the senses, sometimes referred
to as the data of immediate awareness. Some would refer to it as the
immediate mental effect of brain or neural activities resulting from
stimulation of sense organs by the external object. One should however
not mistake them for the cause of perception, so that sense data theory
does not become a causal theory. It should not be taken as causal
especially since we can have instances perceptual relativity, illusion
and hallucination which suggests that even if it will be causal; it
ought to be an adequate cause.[19] We shall now proceed to outline the features of sense datum.
- Sense-data are ‘private’, they are subjective in character. They are
the particular data from the senses in a particular consciousness. By
contrast, physical objects are ‘public’. One and the same table can be
experienced by different people.[ii]
- Sense-data only exist while they are being experienced. An experience must be
experienced by someone to exist at all. A physical object, such as a
table, can exist when no one experiences it. Thus they are temporal.
- Sense-data are exactly as they seem. As we said above, they are
‘appearances’. There is no further reality to an appearance than how it
appears. Physical objects can appear differently from how they really
are (e.g. the stick in water). They have a reality which is not defined
by appearance.[20]
It seems however, that the indirect realists, in Humean terms were
‘multiplying entities unnecessarily’ as it does seem like we would have
to create a new world for these set of entities called ‘sense data’
since it has been shown that they do not reside in the object, neither
do they reside in the perceiver. So the indirect realist faces the
problem of being able to account for a comprehensive nature for these
new set of entities without contradiction.
1.6 Direct Realism vs. Indirect Realism Theory of Perception
The distinction between the tenets of direct realism and the indirect
has so far been clearly defined. We shall make an attempt to account
for the argument of the indirect realists, this shall be included in the
aim of the present section, besides trying to assert an enquiry into
the nature of the divide.
While the argument of the direct realist hinges on the notion of our
ability to directly and immediately perceive the objects of perception,
the arguments of the indirect realists has been an attempt to render
direct realism which of course holds contrary views to them incoherent
and thus unacceptable as an adequate theory of perception. The indirect
realist uses mainly two ‘severe’ critiques against direct realism, which
establishes their own positions as indirect realists. These arguments
include: the argument from illusion and the argument from hallucination.
1.6.1 The Argument from Illusion
In illusions, we perceive objects, but not as they really are. The
most common examples of this kind of a perceptual error is the example
of the bent stick in water which under normal conditions would not be
bent. This kind of argument would seem to undermine direct realism, as
it would then require an extra explanation for this kind of perceptual
error.
Indirect Realist’s Argument: The indirect realist
however is able to conveniently accommodate the notion of a perceptual
error given the concept of ‘sense data’. The argument is that since all
we can really perceive are sense-datum, then whatever we seem to
perceive is not the object but a sense-datum of it, thus it is not the
stick that is bent in water, but only our sense data of it makes it
appear so.
The direct realist would however in an attempt to disprove the
indirect realist claim that the argument from illusion might unsettle
his own tenets, but it is not sufficient to establish the grounds for
indirect realism. If sense data attempt to represent the world to us,
and if they are the only objects of perception, then we ought not to be
able to have illusions, because illusions are cases of what is not
appearing as it is, but since sense data is all we perceive, then how do
we know for sure that it renders an inaccurate representation of the
world beyond it? In fact, since it is the nature of sense data to be
variant and subjective, then how do we really claim to have uniform
knowledge of the external world?
1.6.2 The Argument from Hallucination
If in cases of illusion, we ‘misperceive’, then in hallucinations, we
see something, but nothing which exists, for instance a mirage.
Indirect Realist’s Argument: For the indirect
realist thus, whenever we have instances of perceiving when there really
is no external object behind the perception, then what we perceive
cannot be the object since it does not even exist, but sense datum. Like
the previous one, the direct realist seems pushed into a corner for the
lack of an explanation to this obvious deficiency in his theory, so
once again the indirect realist attempts to establish the foundations of
his notions of sense data by claiming that what we perceive that does
not exist is nothing but sense data for there really is no physical
object behind it.[21]
The direct realist would again attempt a reply, for them; as
much as a version of the argument against the indirect realist in the
argument from illusion can be rendered here as well, one is pushed to
consider the idea behind an hallucination: instances of experiencing
what does not in fact exist. But if sense data is a representation of
the external object, and since it is possible to perceive sense data
when in fact there is nothing is represents, then how could we ascribe
adequate credentials of representation to it? Just as much as to claim
not to have an accurate account of perception is to know what exists
beyond what appears to us (the sense data).
1.7 Conclusion
We see how Locke is justifiably referred to as an indirect realist,
due to his distinction between the different kinds of qualities. The
contemporary arguments for indirect realism and how they introduced the
concept of ‘sense data’ is also looked into. We also try to establish
the boundaries between the arguments of the direct and the indirect
realists with the nature of the controversy in mind and the possible
counter arguments that a direct realist would attempt to use to rescue
their argument.
References
[i]
This is another explanation of his representationalist position since
what the indirect realist claim is that it is not the object we
perceive, but only mediation, a representation of it.
[ii]
We should here remember Locke’s description of the secondary qualities
as being subjective and the primary as being objective and universal.
[1] Anthony Kenny: A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. Clarendon Press: Oxford. Oxford University Press Inc., New York, 2004. p. 50
[2][2] Lacewing, Micheal: Representative Realism.p.1
[5] Hume, David: An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748/1772) 12.8
[6] Lacewing, Micheal: Representative Realism.p.1
[7] Group, T. a. (2014, 07 06). Philosophy for AS. Frances and Taylor Group. p.3
[9] Anthony Kenny: A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. Clarendon Press: Oxford. Oxford University Press Inc., New York, 2004. p. 53
[10] Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. In The Empiricists. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1974, pg. 1.
[12] Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Book II, Chapter I: Of Ideas In General, And Their Original.
[13] Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Book II. Of Ideas in General, And Their Original. Book II
[14] Anthony Kenny: A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. Clarendon Press: Oxford. Oxford University Press Inc., New York, 2004. p. 53
[16] Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Book II. Chapter VIII: Some Further Considerations Concerning Our Simple Ideas of Sensation. Primary Qualities of Bodies. Secondary Qualities of Bodies. Book VIII)
[17] Alfred Weber, The Philosophy of John Locke, pg. 5
[18] Lacewing, Micheal: Representative Realism, pg. 2.
[19] Encyclopedia of Philosophy 7, Sense Data, pg. 478
[20] Lacewing, Micheal: Representative Realism, p.6
[20] Ibid: p. 6
CHAPTER 2
2.0 Introduction
We have in the previous chapter attempted to account for the
arguments of John Locke and how it is that we arrive at our conclusion
of his being an indirect realist from his distinction between primary
and secondary qualities. The aim of the present chapter shall be in
three-folds: a critical assessment of Locke’s representative position, a
look into the subjective idealism of Bishop George Berkeley, influenced
by Locke to propound a thesis that disagrees with common sense, and
finally a critique of the school of indirect realism as a whole.
2.1 A Critical Appraisal of Locke’s Indirect Realism
At the outset, before Locke laid his theory of empiricism, the very
first thing he did was to attempt to debunk the concept of innatism upon
which rationalism was built, so that he may erect his own empirical
theory upon it. We should note that the claim that the concept of
innatism that Locke seemed to radically object against is one that bases
its foundations on the metaphysical concept of God. Some contrary
version of innatism that does not have itself built on a metaphysical
Being who ‘puts’ ideas in our minds at birth is however discernible in
the works of Noam Chomsky.[20]
The contention is that Locke’s critic would only be valid against
innatism of the Cartesian frame of mind, those that seek to ascribe for
the ideas we have at birth to God as the source. This may not be a
critic against Locke’s position, but it is sure an instance of a point
for the rationalists, and a stream of thought worth pursuing. Most
attempts at criticizing Locke’s philosophy come from two major aspects
against his thought. It is either such critic seeks to undermine his
contention that primary and secondary qualities are sufficient to
establish the contents of experience, or it is the case that they seek
to establish that Locke’s conclusion in his concept of substratum or
substance as a concept that exists but yet is that which we ‘know not
what’ is unfounded, and could lead to skepticism. It is an adoption of
both frames of mind however that the philosophy of Bishop Berkeley
adopted in his attempt to undermine the basics of Lockean epistemology.
To begin with, we shall first talk about the concept of matter upon
which Locke lay the existence of primary qualities. In an attempt to
achieve comprehensiveness, and having propounded that there were primary
and secondary qualities, one existing in the object therefore of
necessary significance to its retaining its identity. The other only
produced in the mind of the perceiver by the primary qualities and so
subjective to each perceiver, he found it an essential conclusion to
propound in turn some concept in which these ideas of primary qualities
(if not the secondary) subsist.
For him, the existence of such concept is necessary due to the fact
that the mentioned qualities must have at least a coherent existence in
the external world. Such a concept in which they would exist cannot be
an idea since it is supposed to serve as a kind of pillar to primary and
secondary qualities. The point of Locke’s argument thus necessitated
the existence of the material substratum so that it may hold
both primary and secondary qualities. Thus, following the dictates of
his representationalist empiricism, Locke argued that the qualities we
perceive in the objects of the external world cannot hang in the air and
are in need of a support. He maintained that there must be a substratum
or support to which these qualities are attached.[20]
Locke however claimed that such material thing is that which ‘we know
not what’ because it is not possible to infer the existence of
something outside of the primary qualities that our senses can perceive.
Matter is conceived as an inert, senseless, and unknown substance. This
is why Locke had referred to it as “I know, not what”. Matter neither
acts, nor perceives, nor is perceived and it is mostly made up of
negatives. The only positive supposition about matter is that it is a
“support to qualities”.[20]
If this is the kind of reading that we acquire from Locke, of an
inert matter that cannot act but is only perceivable due to its
possessing the character of upholding primary and secondary qualities,
then this as asserted in the previous chapter is what makes Locke an
indirect realist, so that most if not all the arguments tenable against
indirect realism may be tenable against Locke too. We shall however take
account of some of the objections against Locke’s epistemology.
According to William T. Jones he contends that the indirect realist’s
division of our ideas has a fundamental flaw that is contrary to
experience, Locke laid his notion of “idea” as being constituents of the
mind, he divided these features of the mind into two, the simple and
the complex. While simple ideas are the constituents derived originally
from experience, the complex ones are nothing but combinations of simple
ideas. For instance the simple ideas of a “fish” and a woman compound
to birth the complex idea of a “mermaid”, something not obtainable in
experience. The understanding from here is that when we perceive a
mental idea of an “apple” for instance, what should occur to the
perceiver’s mind should be the simple ideas of red, sweet, and round to
be compounded into the complex idea of an apple. Experience shows
otherwise, for the reverse is the case. It is until the complex idea of
“apple” has been perceived before we are able to arrive at more simple
ideas that are supposed to compound it. It is thus the case that Locke’s
division of ideas into the simple and complex and the features he
ascribed to them will lead to conclusions that are contrary to
experience.[20]
To consider another critique however, this critique seeks to
show how it is that Locke’s position can lead to skepticism about the
existence of material substances. Berkeley substituted Locke’s position
with his idealism so he moving totally away from the realm of matter.
Granted that Locke claims that primary qualities are contained in the
object of perception, it is supposed to be the case that our
understanding of the nature of the substratum in which these
qualities subsist so that we can infer that for the quality to exist,
there must be something in which it subsist. Locke’s position however
will not allow us arrive at that conclusion for he seems to think that
qualities have to exist before we can proceed to the existence of the
matter behind them. And since he ended up being an indirect realist as
explained in the previous chapter, then we are left with no other option
but having to infer the material substance behind said qualities. If
Locke claims that all we perceive are the ideas of primary and secondary
qualities, then the material substance to which these qualities belong
are beyond our experience and so can only be inferred. But experience is
once again contrary to this implication, for there are instances in
which we do not even notice some of the qualities that a material
substance possesses, but notice it in its entirety, as a combination of
the qualities it possesses.[20]
The last of the critics that shall be rendered against
Locke shall be one that seeks to question the causal connection between
physical objects and the ideas of primary and secondary qualities that
they cause. To know that primary qualities exist in the external object
is to know for sure that such physical object exists. For the
explanation of the origin of the qualities is that they exist in the
physical object out there. For Locke however to retract and disclaim
having any relevant knowledge of the object is a curious point to take.
Since existence of the qualities depend upon it, there is no reason to
deny existence to it. If the connection is really a causal one, then to a
large extent there ought to be an adequate account of the cause and the
effect proceeding from such cause.[20]
Having laid several standard critics against Locke, we shall proceed
to the next British empiricist after Locke, Bishop George Berkeley and
his subjective idealism.
2.2 Bishop George Berkeley’s Doctrine of Subjective Immaterialism
Berkeley was an Irishman of theological inclinations, for which
reason he was said to have been a Bishop who contributed to the
philosophy of his era in a way that according to several commentators
today contradict with the dictates of common sense. This is largely due
to the position Berkeley held in his empiricism, a position he derived
from that of John Locke. It is believed that it is in an attempt to push
Locke’s ideas to an extreme in an attempt at criticism that helped
Berkeley arrive at his own thesis on the nature of perception especially
as seen in his New Theory of Vision (1709), An Essay Concerning Principles of Human Knowledge (1710) and The Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonaus (1713).
The point that Berkeley was a Bishop played much role in the
formulation of his thread of empiricism. Previous thoughts had created
problems that could lead to confusions about questions of the world
being based upon the guidance of God the Ultimate Ruler of the Universe.
Berkeley thought that there were three views current in his day that
threatened the Christian faith: the skeptical belief that nothing could
be known for certain, the materialism that comes from Hobbes which
seemed to imply atheism, and the belief, among those that believed in
God, that God had no continuous involvement with the universe.[20] So it
could be surmised that he wanted to argue mainly against atheism as
well as skepticism.
As earlier mentioned, Berkeley turned out being a subjective
idealist, and it was due to his critique of Locke that helped him arrive
at the conclusion that he did. It is this aspect of his thought as an
idealist that we are concentrating upon.
2.2.1 Berkeley’s Critique against Lockean Distinction between Primary and Secondary Qualities
His arguments against Locke’s position as in indirect realism stems
mainly from two aspects of the latter’s philosophy: his claim about the
nature of the existence of matter or substratum and his
distinction between primary and secondary qualities. In fact, most of
his arguments were raised against Locke’s doctrine of material
substratum. He also contends that another thesis that supports the idea
of material substance is the distinction between primary and secondary
qualities.[20]
The attempt at the critique could be seen in his The Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, where
we see Hylas means “wood” in Greek, implying “matter” and the word
”Philonous” a combination of “philo” which means “love” and “nous” which
means, “mind”. Philonous is thus a lover of the mind, who asserts that
every reality is mental.[20] It is from the conversation between these
two that we are able to discern Berekeley’s position on the nature of
the existence of matter.
Locke had divided the various kinds of qualities, and for him
qualities are “the ability of an object to cause ideas in our mind”[20]
we have into two, one he claimed was primary and was supposed to be
“…utterly inseparable from (the) body…”[20] and included solidity,
extension, figure, mobility, bulk, weight, and texture, it is their
character to exist even without the perception of some being of them
since they are in the material object of perception and are
thus said to be objective. The secondary qualities however differ from
the primary on the grounds that they are the representations that the
mind perceives in objects, they include color, taste, smell, sound,
[felt] temperature and are caused in us by primary qualities, thus they
are an topic of the mind and are subjective. This distinction ran Locke
into a wall because it helped give Berkeley the right to accuse him of
having contradicted himself.
It is however until we note the Lockean comment that even primary
qualities are ideas in the mind. Locke recognizes this and affirms that
they are in the object and also in the mind since they are qualities,
and are in their nature mental.[20] Let us consider that the ideas of
extension and solidity for instance which are stated to be primary
qualities and hence are understood as the original qualities that belong
to the material substance. These are also gained through the sense of
touch and hence are sensations in the mind. We cannot separate the idea
of extension from the idea of color and other so-called secondary
qualities. When we perceive anything extended we perceive it as colored
and having other secondary qualities also. Going by his own distinction
between the two, this would ordinarily amount to a contradiction, which
Berkeley subscribes to.[20] To claim that they exist both in the object
and the mind might amount not just to a contradiction in Berkeley, but
also help achieve a unity of the ideas of both primary and secondary
qualities since both exist in the mind, thus for Berkeley, all we have
are qualities and so there is no distinction between primary and
secondary qualities.
Berkeley believed that the weakest point in this whole philosophical
edifice was the very notion of matter, conceived of as some sort of
mind-independent stuff adequately characterizable in terms of the
so-called primary qualities alone.[20]
If Locke is going to ascribe to the material substance that
supposedly upholds the qualities features of being unknown, then it will
imply that every quality of an object can be reduced to a sensible
quality or to a sensation, and these are supposed to be conscious in the
sense of being perceivable which will be an ability they are endowed
with and immaterial. Berkeley argues that there is nothing beyond
sensations and hence every reality is mental. To put it in another way,
let us consider that Berkeley seeks to hold that the idea of a material
substance that could possibly exist behind the qualities independent of
the mind may pose the threat of atheism and irreligion. Because it
implies an independent material substance inert, incapable of acting.
But when we experience, we do get some form of data from the external
world. These datum cannot arise from the matter of Locke, so it must
have an alternate source, this could only be qualities. These qualities
are not inert in nature. So an adequate condition for perception is that
that which we perceive must be active as much as the mind is. And in
being active cannot be material, it therefore has to be some immaterial
thing. Since we cannot deny that we perceive, then whatever it is we
perceive cannot but be an idea, all of our experience is composed of
active non-physical events, they are the real contents of not just
experience, but the external world. And in the above fashion, we
establish Berkeley’s immaterialism.
Admittedly, the argument as outlined above justifying Berkeley’s
immaterialism is held to be contrary to common-sense. However, we cannot
deny the conclusion he had arrived at, perhaps impracticable, but the
only conclusion to which he could push Locke’s position. We shall now
proceed to explain Berkeley’s subjectivism.
According to Berkeley, a mind is a mind because it contains ideas,
this is because what defines its nature as a mind is because of the
ideas it contains, or the fact that it contains them at all. As much as
ideas do not have an independent existence outside of the mind. Thus,
for an idea to be, it must be the contents of the experience of some
mind. Then for existence to be ascribed to a particular thing, it has to
first exist in some mind. So Berkeley’s most famous saying that esse est percipii
meaning ‘to be is to be perceived’ –by a mind, can be observed from
this stream of thought. This would mean that existence is subjective to
some mind. This is apparent in his famous analogy during the
conversation between Hylas and Philonous in the Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. We
are invited to imagine an instance of an object existing unperceived
such as a tree in a forest for instance. For Hylas, it will be
impossible think about an object that is not the subject of the mind of
some perceiver. Because
…as I was thinking of a tree in a solitary place, where no one was
present to see it, methought that was to conceive a tree as existing
unperceived or unthought of, not considering that I myself conceived it
all the while.[20]
To think of the tree is to have it is the subject of the perception of whatever mind is doing the thinking.
Since existence is mind-dependent for Berkeley, it will be impossible
to have an instance of an existing but unperceived idea. The
characteristics of the mind too include that it is not objective but
subjective. This is from Cartesian as well as Lockean thoughts.[20] And
since Berkeley’s argument about how he ended up an idealist has been
established, then it will mean the contents of our mind dependent
perceptions are nothing but ideas, hence his subjective idealism.
In an effort at being comprehensive however, Berkeley says that
perhaps our perception might be mind-dependent such that what exists
only really does as much as it is the subject of the perception of a
mind. He postulated an infinite mind from which all ideas project, this
necessitated that God exist thus because God is seen to be infinite so
will His mind be, and if that is the case, then the mind of God is the
infinite mind, while that of man is finite. So, in instances of my
leaving my room, that I am not in the room and therefore not perceiving
the room does not mean that the room will stop existing, it will exist
as much as it is the object of perception of the mind of God.
The next thing to do now is to attempt a critical assessment of Berkeley.
2.3 Critical Assessment of Berkeley’s Argument
“…few idealists after Berkeley argued for idealism. Instead, they argue from idealism.”
- David Stove, Idealism: A Victorian Horror-Story (Part Two)[20]
2.3.1 The Problem of Objectivity
The critique was rendered by Bruce W. Hauptli in his Selected Criticisms of Berkeley for British Empiricism. As
much as the critic seeks to show how the problem of objectivity would
exist for Berkeley and anyone who subscribes to his theory and the
derived conclusion, we shall attempt to add a new twist to Hauptli’s
original critique.
“If I perceive a table, it exists. If Fred perceives a table, it
exists. What ensures that we see the same table? Given that one has
only one’s own sensation to go on, why assume that these are shared by
others i.e. that there is a common world?”[20]
The understanding derivable from this question is that of the claim
that Berkeley’s position wrongly assumes that different perceivers of a
particular object perceive the same thing. But since we do not have the
same minds, then on what grounds could such an assumption as this be
articulated?
Granted that the mind and ideas are the only things existing in
Berkeley’s epistemology. To perceive something therefore will imply that
the object of perception is an idea and therefore a constituent of the
mind. It has to be of a subjective character. If that is the case, then
it will mean that no two perceivers can perceive the same thing, since
they do not have the same medium of perception. My subjective experience
is unique as much as it is totally inaccessible from some other
person’s, it is therefore closed. The implication will be that since two
people observing the same ‘idea’ are only perceiving just that, how
does one account for the difference in the nature of their perceptions?
One reply is to say that we go by the primary quality of extension (that
an object is identical to itself as long as it occupies the portion of
space it does and none other), or perhaps are we to go by saying that
they do not differ but are similar?
If we are to adopt the first kind of reply of the primary quality of
extension and so imply a difference, then it will mean that the objects
of perception have to occupy some portion of space, before we can only
assign to them notions of difference on those grounds. But we do not
want to go by that because even Berkeley would not, for the reason that
in talking about occupying space, then we speak already of not an idea
now, but a material substance existence for which Berkeley had initially
denied. To the other reply therefore, that they are similar will imply
some notion of objectivity, for it will mean that although proceeding
from differing minds, the ideas in these minds are similar. Now several
things can be from here implied, one will be that to claim that they are
similar is to say that they must have been to some extent compared
against each other, and if that is the case then it will contradict
their initial nature in being subjective.
For human beings such as ourselves to exist in the same society, it
presupposes that there is to some extent a universal underlying
character of experience to which each person is a member of and thus
would be able to relate to, and with. To deny this point is to deny the
fundamental character of human beings where they are projected as social
animals. But Berkeley’s position will never allow the existence of this
fundamental universals and so would need to posit for his theory an
account of how our ideas being subjective, shuts one off from every
other’s experiences and yet we obviously exist in the same societies.
We should however note that Berkeley might render a reply in the
guise of claiming that it is in the nature of the subjective feature of
the mind to differ for the simple fact that it is subjective. But we
should not forget that all of the ideas that is constituted in the mind
of each perceiver proceeds from just one source: the infinite mind. As
much as these ideas proceed from the mind of God, then that the claim
that there is no universal source from which our ideas emerge will be
rendered devoid of some of its potency. The mind of God unites all the
others in the sense of being the origin of the contents of each mind and
being the mind to which each and every other mind partakes.
2.3.2 The Avoidance of Universals
The foundations of this present argument can be seen in Hillary Putnam’s After Empiricism,
and it involved an analysis of Berkeley’s notion of idea, it is worthy
of note that this argument can also be rendered against the later
empiricist and skeptic David Hume but since Hume is not currently in our
purview, we shall only extort how the argument is relevant against
Berkeley.
For Berkeley, there cannot be a ‘general idea’ or an ‘abstract idea’
of the color ‘green’, to ascribe to an idea ‘green’ whether it is a
color patch as existing in my mind or a token of the word ‘green’ when
such an idea is used for the whole class of green sense-data in the mind
, what really happens is that we have in one way or the other compared
this particular token with some other tokens in the mind for which we
have accepted are ‘green’, and we have in essence claimed that it is
similar to them or they are similar to one another. However, to think of
a relation of similarity is to assume that there exists universals,
because for there to be a comparison between two things, it implies that
we think there is a high chance that they are the same, to think so is
to assume that they have something in common.[20] All the worst for
Berkeley if our comparison comes out successful, where we are able to
establish that these ideas are really similar and therefore there must
exist some kind of ocean from which all things green are a part of, and a
nature of it which they possess, a notion that Berkeley never
accommodated.
Much like in the first argument, the reply of Berkeley to this second
critic will be that as long as there is an infinite mind that perceives
even in the absence of the finite mind, then there can be a universal
source from which all ideas of color emerge, and because this provision
is available, then that each perceiver perceives a similar color green
is an effect of being visited with the same idea by the infinite mind.
2.3.3 The Argument from Perceptual Errors
An adequate assessment of the argument of Berkeley shows an
inadequacy of a different kind now, one that the indirect realists
showed was the inadequacy ascribed to direct realism, why it was proven
to be faulty and thus necessitating an alternate theory to account for
the nature of perception. It is a perceptual fact that there are
hallucinations and illusions, these are perceptual errors where
perceiver seems to perceive an object having specific features in
experience when in actual fact it does not, it either does not exist at
all in the case of an hallucination or does not exist as possessing the
features experience shows it possessing.
For any comprehensive theory of perception, there has to be an
account of notions of this kind, so that it is an adequate theory in
being able to accommodate the shortcomings that come with subscribing to
such as an empiricist’s leniency towards direct and naïve realism.
Direct realism claims that the immediate object of perception
is the physical object itself. We don’t perceive it in virtue of
perceiving something else that ‘mediates’ between our minds and the
object[20], thus the argument from illusion became valid against them
since illusion entails misperceiving an object as having qualities it
does not in fact have. When indirect realism came onto the scene
however, we are invited to consider an alternative theory where there
are mental data called sense data between perceiver and perceived, an
account of illusions and hallucinations thus will include mention of
such private sense data as the explanation for the perceptual errors.
In the Berkely-ian system however, there is no account of an
explanation for illusions or hallucinations, all he wanted to account
for was the relationship between the mind that does the perceiving and
the idea that is the object of perception. This renders his system
inadequate on the grounds that he does not take account of perceptual
errors that cannot be denied as one of the many flaws of the school of
empiricism.
2.4 Conclusion
We have seen the nature of the critics against Locke’s indirect
realism and how they attempt to undermine his position. The classical
critic regardless is found in Berkeley who based the foundations of his
anti-common sense subjective idealism on the extremities discernible
from Locke’s position in asserting that there is no distinction between
primary and secondary qualities, because both can be in the mind and are
thus mental, so that all we have left are ideas since Locke had not
strictly delineated his conception of the substratum or matter.
We have also seen how Berkeley’s position is on the main
refused due to the conclusions of his argumentation, letting himself be
guided by the tenets of his theology, he laid all evidence and origin of
ideas on the metaphysical concept of God, so that he became even more
vulnerable than his idealism allowed.
References
[20] Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly, IIT Madras. Aspects of Western Philosophy. New Delhi, 2005. Document. p. 3
[20] Ibid: 3
[20] Ibid p. 5
[20] W.T. Jones, Hobbes to Hume: A History of Western Philosophy (second edition) (N.Y. Harcourt Brace, 1969), pp. 243-244
[20] Lacewing, Micheal. Indirect Realism. London: Routledge Taylor and Francis Group, 2005. 9
[20] Ibid: 12
[20]
[20] Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly, IIT Madras. Aspects of Western Philosophy. New Delhi, 2005. Document. p. 2
[20] Ibid: 2
[20] Anthony Kenny: A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. Clarendon Press: Oxford. Oxford University Press Inc., New York, 2004. p. 53
[20] Ibid: 53
[20] Ibid: 57
[20] Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly, IIT Madras. Aspects of Western Philosophy. New Delhi, 2005. Document. p. 6
[20] Lowe, E.J. Lowe Philosophical Guidebook to Locke On Human Understanding. New York: Francis and Taylor Group, 1995. pp. 53
[20] Benneth, Jonathan. Bishop George Berkeley :Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. London: Oxford University Press, 2004. Dialogue 3; pp. 42
[20]Bruce W. Hauptli. Selected Criticisms of Berkeley for British Empiricism. pp. 2
[20] Ibid: 2
[20] Hilary Putnam. After Empiricism, Realism With A Human Face (Cambridge: Harvard U.P., 1990), pp. 43-53
[20] Lacewing, Micheal: Representative Realism. p. 3
CHAPTER 3
3.0 Introduction
In contrast to direct realism, the indirect or representationalist
holds an opposing position, for them, the objects of perception are not
mind-independent physical objects. In light of this, the
representationalist holds two main theses: first, that what is perceived
directly or immediately in sensory experience is not some “external” physical or material object, but rather things that are mental or subjective in character—sense-data, according to the most standard versions of the view. Second that the only available reasons deriving from perception for thinking that perceptual beliefs about the physical world are true depend on inference from facts[20].
The current chapter is an attempt to consider some of the critiques
rendered against representative realism and the implications that can be
derived from there. An attempt will also be taken to synthesize the
positions of Locke and Berkeley on the argument from the nature of
primary and secondary qualities and Locke’s substratum. Subsequently, the arguments of Hume with special emphasis on the nature of causation in Locke is taken account of.
3.1 Arguments against the Representationalist Theory of Perception
That the indirect realists have from the objections recognized
against the arguments of the direct realists delineated an alternate
theory of perception for themselves is not sufficient justification for
their position, we shall on this ground, recognize some of the arguments
against indirect realism.
3.1.1 Sense Data and Reference
The first question we must ask is this: what is a mental
representation? To answer this we must first consider an inherent fact
about human beings: we are intentional agents. That is, our mental
states—beliefs, imaginations, desires, thoughts perceptions, etc.—refer to or are about things.
Also, we can say that a mental state is intentional if there is some
object to which it is directed. So, for example, if I have a ‘desire to
go to the mall’ it will be an intentional mental state with an object
that it refers to, viz. the mall. But it is also something else. It is a
propositional attitude; I have a mental posture towards the
content of my intentional state. Thus, if X desires that P, X is said to
have a propositional attitude towards P. My attitude towards the object
is a ‘desiring-relation’ that I go to that object i.e. the mall.
From the above, we understand that our subjective mental feature in
sense data is not a complete account of our perception until it has
something, some object to which it refers. However, since the character
of our mental experience is such that what we directly perceive is sense
datum, it is difficult to admit into our scheme of understanding some
notion of mental features having some character to which they refer.
From the Cartesian distinction between mind and body, we are told that
the mind in being res cogitans[20] is
unextended unlike the body. This means that it does not occupy space or
time. If we are to accept this Cartesian description as valid, the
question that arises therefore is whether it is a valid assertion to
claim that such mental character as our sense data has something to
which it refers.
On the same line of thought, if it is the case
that our mental states have some kind of intentionality in having
something to which they refer, and as well possess some notion of
existence because we express propositional attitudes about them, then is
it not the case that what we refer our proposition to is not the
physical object to which we wish to refer, but the mental picture that
appears in our mind? It is curious whether Descartes had this contention
in mind when he laid the foundation for the Cartesian dualism that
persists till today. Regardless, it remains a curious turn of events to
refer to mental features the way we would to material substances.
3.1.2 The Argument from Causation
Granted that the representationalist in promoting his
version of perception has made a distinction between physical objects in
the outside world, and the mental characters that appears to us in
experience. Since they are only obvious to the mind of the perceiver we
say that they are mind-dependent. If the nature of perceptual experience
is constituted by the subject’s acquaintance with mind-dependent direct
objects distinct from mind-independent physical objects, then how is
such experience supposed to constitute a source of knowledge about the
presence and nature of any such physical objects themselves? The
representationalist might have as well claimed that what exists out
there is the mental character to which experience restricts us, behind
which they claim the existence of a physical world to which no access
regardless is granted. This will lead us to a very idealist conclusion
as we see in British empiricist Bishop George Berkeley who in an attempt
to push to logical conclusions the argument of John Locke, claimed
non-existence to the physical object behind mental perception of mental
features like sense data.
The potency of the criticism is realized once we note that the claim
of the direct realists who, because of their assertion that physical
objects are the direct objects of perception, can end up being a causal
theory of perception. This is because, they will be saying that our
perception is caused. The same level of criticism can be
rendered against the representationalist only a less acceptable version,
since they will in essence be claiming that there is a relationship of
causation between perceiver and perceived. The only premise is that the
cause of our perception is not a physical object but a mental feature.
3.1.3 Illusion and Hallucination Revisited
In the previous chapter, we had established to an extent how it is
the case that the arguments from illusion and hallucination as rendered
against the direct realists sometimes, in fact most times helps inform
the foundational construct upon which representationalism stands. To
avoid taking the long journey down the lines of reiteration, the
argument goes something like this:
- In a hallucination, we perceive something having some property F.
2. When we perceive something having some property F, then there is something that has this property.
3. We don’t perceive a physical object at all.
4. Therefore, what we perceive must be mental – sense-data.
5. Hallucinations can be experiences that are ‘subjectively indistinguishable’ from real perceptions.
6. Therefore, we see the same thing, namely sense-data, in both hallucinations and real perception.
7. Therefore, in all cases, we see sense-data, and not physical objects, immediately.
8. Therefore, direct realism is false.[20]
It is ironical that this argument, as its viciousness would go is one
supposed to be relevant against the direct realist, it could however be
as vicious and perhaps even more once it is turned around and rendered
against the representationalist.
Granted that the representationalist claims that what we perceive in
cases of perception is not the physical object itself, but sense data
which is described to be mental. If this is to be held as a valid
assertion, then in cases of illusion and hallucination, it proves
nothing. That the mental character perceived is nothing like the
physical object behind it shows that we know what the physical object
looks like. For the perceiver to claim to know that he has an illusion
or a hallucination, he must to some extent know of the nature of the
external object behind the sense data he supposedly perceives in
illusions and know that they do not exist in hallucinations. Knowing
that the physical object reports a different account of experience from
the sense data is at least evidence of its existence, that the
representationalist would stubbornly decide to hold on to that which
emits from the object therefore amounts to self-deceit, for then not
only can we perceive the mental feature, but there is a physical feature
behind this subjective state that causes the mental and reports a
different reality.
3.1.4 The Representationalist as a Solipsist
The last objection that will be rendered against the
representationalist is that their position can lead to solipsism.
Solipsism is the doctrine that only we possess minds, and in some other
variant, some solipsists hold that maybe other beings have minds, we
cannot know for sure that they think at all, or if they do that they
think the way we do.[20]
The character of our mental experience is subjective, this is one of
the other features that we inherit from the famous Cartesian
distinction. If the representationalist would be claiming that sense
data is the object of direct perception, then they would be claiming
that what we perceive is evident to only us, so that others will not
perceive what we do and the nature of the objective fact behind the
subjective experience is ruined.
To the variant of representationalist that claims that we do not
perceive physical objects directly, it could be argued that such an
assertion is curious, for it will lead to a revival of the Berkeley-ian
doctrine of “to be is to be perceived” so that what exists can only be
said to exist because there is a mind that perceives it. If this will
hold, then it disqualifies the representationalist as an empiricist
since the nature of sense experience is not subjective like the strict
subjectivity we get from the mind but to an extent objective. And in
being an objective fact out there renders the representationalist on
another ground an idealist and also a solipsist since sense data is only
obvious to our perceptual framework the way they are and to none
others.
3.2 A Synthesis of Locke’s and Berkeley’s Positions
Much like philosophy in antiquity, where we see the efforts of the
post-Eleatic philosophers to deny Eleatic monism. And so rendering their
own postulations in the shadows of the foremost Eleatic who had in his
ontology claimed that space could not exist because it enabled “what is”
to become “what is-not”. They went ahead in succession to postulate
first, a theory that allowed motion without space as in Empedocles, and
then one that allowed both motion and space as in Atomism, according to
Leucippus and Democritus[20]. So it obtains in the relationship between
the foremost of the British empiricists, John Locke and Bishop
Berkeley.
The epistemological groundwork of both theories is the fact that they
are both empiricists. This enables us to make some valid assertions as
to the nature of Locke’s theory in the light of that of Berkeley. Their
being both empiricists of course implies that they both subscribe to the
version of ideas according to which the mind at birth is a blank slate,
in contrast to what a rationalist such as Descartes may claim in
asserting the innatists’ position.
The synthesis between Locke and Berkeley shall be recognized on several grounds, and these include:
3.2.1 On the Distinction between Primary and Secondary Qualities
Granted that Berkeley’s critic of Locke was informed pathway in his
claim that there are no distinctions between primary and secondary
qualities. Partly because even Locke had claimed that they both exist in
the mind of the perceiver even if he will deny all manners of coherent
existence to the substratum behind said qualities, but more
because Berkeley due to his eventual position as an idealist cannot
claim existence for primary qualities - there is no substratum in
which they would subsist, there is no material object to hold them
together and which should serve as their support. Also in consideration
of the fact that Berkeley claims that only two things exist: minds and
ideas, then it will be necessary for the primary as well as the
secondary qualities not to exist in the external world, but in the mind
of the perceiver.[20]
In the light of the fact therefore that Locke had implied it, since
even the mind according to him could put together simple and complex
ideas. Which ordinarily contain both primary and secondary qualities,
then there is no valid reason why a material object is required for the
existence of the primary qualities. One could say therefore that
Berkeley only wanted to say what Locke did not say, or could not have
finished saying.
3.2.2 On the Nature of Substratum
In an arguably rare moment of skepticism, and perhaps to withhold an
assertive position on the nature of the external world behind the
primary qualities Locke said exist, Berkeley had withdrawn making bold
assertions. Having ascribed to the nature of experience and the senses
the abilities that Locke had done, he could not proceed to lay the
foundations and the support for primary qualities in the external
object, so that modern commentators and historians are able to
conveniently categorize him as saying what we perceive is not the
physical object behind the primary qualities, but nothing beyond these
qualities. We can only go ahead to infer in conformity with experience
that there must be some place where these qualities exist together
before they are presented to us in experience. This was how he ended up
an indirect realist, or a representationalist.
When Berkeley came to the scene however, he showed us that what Locke
could have said but did not was that our inference of the external
object is not sufficient evidence of its existence, such that since only
the primary and secondary qualities can be perceived, then they are the
ones that we can validly make claims and so assert existence to. It
seemed therefore that Locke was saying tacitly that what exists in the
world was primary qualities, and the material behind it, according to
him was “that which we know not of” and nothing more than this can be
said of it.
Now, granted that Locke had handed over to Berkeley the relevant
ropes of his own criticism, it enabled Berkeley to push out of the table
of existence, Locke’s “that which I know not of” so he could claim sufficiently that it was God who was the author of the ideas in our minds, making his doctrine of esse est percippii.
The same concept of understanding we shall be imposing upon Locke, thus
for him that primary and secondary qualities exist, then we can say
that their existence is not necessarily dependent upon any notion of substratum.
This is seen to be relevant especially in the light of Locke’s
inability to say any other thing other than that the primary and
secondary qualities must have somewhere in which they subsist. If that
is the case, then it is not a necessary criterion that substance must
exist before the qualities do, since they are shown to be ideas in the
minds of the perceiver both primary and secondary.
The implication will be that while Locke might not affirm God as the
origin of his own ideas, as long as he is able to say that even primary
qualities are subjective, then Berkeley’s position of subjectivity can
be imposed upon him. And for as long as he cannot lay any more claim
about the necessary existence of substratum other than that it
holds primary and secondary qualities together, then the fact that it
can be shown that these qualities exist in the mind of the perceiver
kills the necessity raised. So, matter or substance does not require an
existence because of the subjectivity of the qualities in Berkeley as
much as in Locke.
3.3 My Position on the Issue
While Locke had attempted to articulate his argument on the nature of
the existence of both primary and secondary qualities and the material
substance he could not deny behind them, it raised questions in his
epistemology. For instance he had to explain how substratum,
which he could not say much abouts be the “pillar” behind the existence
of primary and secondary qualities. This has an implication for Lockean
philosophy.
Let us consider his argument in a new light. If it is the case that
qualities are nothing but “the ability of an object to cause ideas in
our mind”[20], the implication will be that since it is this object that
causes the qualities, then it means that the object from which the
qualities emerge pre-suppose the existence of the qualities. For the
qualities to exist because they are emissions from the object, then it
means this object as a special causal power, and this is the quality.
But for the causal power to even be at all, this material object had to
first exist. It is because it exists that it is able to cause the ideas
that it causes in our minds. Those that Locke claimed are resident in
the object which are the primary qualities. It is surprising then that
Locke would return to deny existence to the cause of the qualities. From
this line of argument, the implication will be that if the object
cannot be said to certainly exist, then on what grounds can we say that
primary and secondary qualities have a causal base in the external
world? We will have no right to say that. And if that is the case, then
we might as well be saying that from sensation, there can be no data,
and therefore in reflection there can be no ideas.
On a different ground, if Locke claims that the object “causes” ideas
in our mind, one might want to take him up on his usage of the word
“cause”.
David Hume, in his An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
had laid down the conditions that must exist before one can say that
there is a causal relation between two events: cause and effect. For
him, for an event to cause another, there must first exist the condition
of spatio-temporal priority which means that the cause must come before
the effect. Secondly is the position of spatio-temporal contiguity,
which states that cause and effect must be close to each other in space.
And then the third condition of spatio-temporal simultaneity which
states that cause and effect must be close to each other in time. The
final undiscoverable condition of Hume however was the idea of necessary
connection which could not be discovered a priori and neither could it be discovered a posteriori
leading Hume into the problem of induction.[20] If we are to consider
these conditions against Locke’s idea of causation, another problem can
be brought out.
For the object to cause ideas which we refer to as qualities, these
conditions must be satisfied between both concepts of object and
qualities. The condition of spatio-temporal priority has been
established already, although it leads Locke into a deeper problem on
its own independent of the others. The condition of spatio-temporal
contiguity cannot be established. This is because cause: the object and
the effect: qualities cannot be observed to be close or far away from
each other for the fact that the qualities only obtain in the mind.
While the cause (the object) is a mere inference from the external
world. The condition of spatio-temporal simultaneity can also not be
examined for the simple fact that we cannot observe any notion of time
between our perceptions of the effect and be able to supply an inference
of matter behind them. The concept of time definitely does not play any
part here, since it will only have us saying we know what the material
object looks like which Locke was trying not to say. The idea of
necessary connection cannot be discovered as well. Because it seems that
Locke has taken a reverse step in the light of what Hume’s contention
is.
Hume says that because we could observe the causes, we are able to
infer and sometimes observe the effects. For Locke however, our
perception of the effect (qualities) is what helps us infer the cause: substratum.
One can say therefore that Locke’s epistemology is not a relevant
account of perception for the reason that it is contrary to experience.
And this undermines Locke’s position as an empiricist.
No matter how much strength one says the argument of Berkeley has, it
can still be criticized. The fact that Locke had already said that
matter is “that which he knows not what” is not sufficient reason to
assume that it does not exist. This is an unfair assumption on the part
of Berkeley. Locke did not imply he was an idealist in any aspect of his
work, otherwise he would not have attempted postulating concepts of
primary qualities which are subjective in nature. Although one may still
criticize Locke on his saying that they are perceptible mentally since
they are ideas.
The implication is that Berkley’s idealism is an unfair attempt to push
Locke’s materialism to a conclusion that Locke does not agree with.
3.4 Conclusion
Locke’s epistemology although considered an adequate theory of
perception by the proponents of the position of representationalism that
he had established is not devoid of its faults. On one hand it could be
shown to be subsumable under the accounts of Berkeley by attempting a
synthesis of both positions. But regardless, Berkeley’s position is not
an adequate conclusion to which Locke’s argument could be pushed. And on
the other hand it was shown to be unable to stand up to the account of
causation recognized in Hume.
This shows that Locke’s account although a brilliant contribution, is
objectionable especially in the light of post-Lockean accounts.
References
[20] Bonjour, Laurence. In Search of Direct Realism. Washington D.C: University of Washington, n.d. p. 3
[20] Descartes, Rene. "Meditations on First Philosophy." Descartes, Rene. The Philosophical Works of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1641. 1-33.
[20] Group, Taylor and Frances. Philosophy for AS. Frances and Taylor Group, 06 07 2014. p. 24
[20] Searle, John. Mind. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.p.16
[20] Kenny, Anthony. A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. New York: Oxford University PressInc.,, 2004.
[20] Ibid: 57
[20] Anthony Kenny: A New History of Western Philosophy: Volume 1: Ancient Philosophy. Clarendon Press: Oxford. Oxford University Press Inc., New York, 2004. p. 53
[20] Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1902.